Quantum Mechanics – How the Copenhagen and Everett Interpretations Make the Same Predictions

foundationsmeasurement-problemquantum mechanicsquantum-foundationsquantum-interpretations

Suppose we have a spin $\frac{1}{2}$ particle in the spin-up state along the $z$-axis, $\lvert \uparrow \rangle$, and after $t$ seconds of evolution under the Schrodinger equation it is in state $\alpha\lvert \uparrow \rangle + \beta\lvert \downarrow \rangle$. Now, according to the Copenhagen interpretation, if we measure its spin along the $z$-axis, there is a probability $\lvert \alpha \rvert ^{2}$ that the state collapses to $\lvert \uparrow \rangle$ and a probability $\lvert \beta \rvert ^{2}$ that it collapses to $\lvert \downarrow \rangle$. Then, after a further $t$ seconds, the state will be $\alpha\lvert \uparrow \rangle + \beta\lvert \downarrow \rangle$ with probability $\lvert \alpha \rvert ^{2}$ and $\gamma\lvert \uparrow \rangle + \delta\lvert \downarrow \rangle$ with probability $\lvert \beta \rvert ^{2}$ for some $\gamma$ and $\delta$. Therefore, if we measure the particle's spin along the $z$-axis again, the probability that we will find it to be spin-up is $\lvert \alpha \rvert ^{4}+\lvert \beta \rvert ^{2}\lvert \gamma\rvert ^{2}$.

I am trying to understand the Everettian interpretation of quantum mechanics. According to the Everettian view as I understand it, after we make our first "measurement" in the scenario above, our measurement device and the particle would be entangled with a joint state of $\alpha\lvert \uparrow \rangle\lvert\frac{1}{2}\rangle + \beta\lvert \downarrow \rangle\lvert-\frac{1}{2}\rangle$, where $\lvert\frac{1}{2}\rangle$ and $\lvert-\frac{1}{2}\rangle$ are supposed to represent the states of the measuring device corresponding to it having measured spin-up and spin-down respectively. Before our second measurement then, our system would presumably be in the state $\alpha^{2}\lvert \uparrow \rangle \lvert\frac{1}{2}\rangle + \beta\gamma\lvert \uparrow \rangle\lvert-\frac{1}{2}\rangle + \alpha\beta\lvert \downarrow \rangle \lvert\frac{1}{2}\rangle + \beta\delta\lvert \downarrow \rangle\lvert-\frac{1}{2}\rangle$. Now, when we make our second measurement, the system is still supposed to evolve under the Schrodinger equation, which is linear, so to work out what will happen, we can just work out what state we would have ended up with if the state had initially been each of the four parts of our superposition and then take the appropriate linear combination. For example, if the initial state had been $\beta\gamma\lvert \uparrow \rangle\lvert-\frac{1}{2}\rangle$, then, we would presumably have ended up with the state $\beta\gamma\lvert \uparrow \rangle\lvert\frac{1}{2}\rangle$, up to some phase, after we brought our measuring device and our particle back together. By this logic, it would seem that we would end up in the state $\left(\alpha^{2} + e^{i\theta_{1}}\beta\gamma\right)\lvert \uparrow \rangle\lvert\frac{1}{2}\rangle + \left(e^{i\theta_{2}}\alpha\beta + e^{i\theta_{3}}\beta\delta\right)\lvert \downarrow \rangle\lvert-\frac{1}{2}\rangle$ for some $\theta_{1}$, $\theta_{2}$ and $\theta_{3}$. The probability of measuring spin-up on our second measurement would apparently then be $\lvert\alpha^{2} + e^{i\theta_{1}}\beta\gamma\rvert^{2}$.

If so, the predictions of the Copenhagen and Everettian interpretations of quantum mechanics could be in agreement with one another only if the Schrodinger equation made sure that $\theta_{1}$ was such that $\lvert \alpha \rvert ^{4}+\lvert \beta \rvert ^{2}\lvert \gamma\rvert ^{2} = \lvert\alpha^{2} + e^{i\theta_{1}}\beta\gamma\rvert^{2}$, i.e. $\Re\left({\alpha^{*}}^{2}e^{i\theta_{1}}\beta\gamma\right) = 0$. My questions then are:

  1. Is my above argument correct?
  2. If so, does the Schrodinger equation make sure the phases are such that the predictions of the two interpretations agree and how can I see that it does so or does not?

Best Answer

The many worlds interpretation (MWI) involves working out the implications of quantum mechanics without modifying it to include collapse.

In the MWI if you make a measurement in general the measurement device becomes correlated not just with the measured system but with many other systems, such as photons reflected from the measurement device, air molecules, grains of dust and so on: these other systems are called the environment. So if you have a system $S$, a measurement device $M$ and an environment $E$ you actually end up with the evolution: $$(\alpha|\uparrow\rangle_S+\beta|\downarrow\rangle_S)|0\rangle_M|0\rangle_E\to \alpha|\uparrow\rangle_S|\uparrow\rangle_M|\uparrow\rangle_E+\beta|\downarrow\rangle_S|\downarrow\rangle_M|\downarrow\rangle_E$$

There is no unitary evolution on $S$ and $M$ that will undo their entanglement with the environment and the environment isn't under our control. There is a large literature on this effect under the name of decoherence:

https://arxiv.org/abs/1111.2189

https://arxiv.org/abs/0707.2832

So doing the kind of experiment you describe requires isolating $S$ and $M$ from the environment In particular it means that there can't be any record at all outside of $S$ and $M$ of the results of the previous measurement.

You ask about the predictions of the Copenhagen interpretation (CI). The CI doesn't specify the mechanism by which the collapse takes place, which makes its predictions vague at best. There are theories that specify mechanisms of collapse, such as spontaneous collapse theories, and those theories in general make different predictions than quantum mechanics:

https://arxiv.org/abs/2310.14969

There are unsolved problems for such theories that don't exist in the MWI:

https://arxiv.org/abs/2205.00568

Related Question