[Math] Why is it easier to prove $e$ is transcendental than $\pi$

transcendencetranscendental-number-theory

Why is it easier to prove $e$ is transcendental than $\pi$?

I noticed that the proofs of $\pi$'s transcendence are much longer and have more details to check than those of $e.$ My guess is that it's simply because the infinite series for $e$ is much simpler and easier to work with than any series for $\pi$, but I wanted to see if there was more to it, so I asked my professor a few weeks ago as he was going over some bonus proofs of transcendence (including $\pi$ and $e$) thrown in at the end of a Galois theory textbook. He said he couldn't really see a philosophical justification for why one should be easier than the other.

Has this question been addressed in the literature, and if so, what do the transcendental number theory experts have to say about it?

Best Answer

This is not a complete answer, but I would say that the "standard" way to prove the transcendence of $\pi$ is as a corollary of the more general fact that $e^\alpha$ is transcendental for all nonzero algebraic $\alpha$. For general $\alpha$, one has to come up with a general method for dealing with those pesky algebraic numbers in the exponent. But for $\alpha=1$, clever ad hoc arguments are possible. For example, in the book Making Transcendence Transparent by Burger and Tubbs (which I highly recommend as a source for further details), they show how to write down explicitly a polynomial $\mathcal{P}_n(z)$ such that $\mathcal{P}_n(1), \mathcal{P}_n(2), \ldots, \mathcal{P}_n(d)$ provide exceptionally good rational approximations to $e, e^2, \ldots, e^d$ respectively. This proof does exploit special properties of the series $\sum_n z^n\!/n!$ so this perhaps vindicates your intuition that $e$ is easier because we have a nicer series for $e$ than for $\pi$. On the other hand, this argument is a bit circular, because isn't $${\pi \over 4} = 1 - {1\over 3} + {1\over 5} - {1\over 7} + \cdots$$ a "nice" formula for $\pi$? Well, maybe, but it's not "nice" in a way that lets us prove transcendence! Hmmm…

So I think that the answer is that we don't know of a way to prove the transcendence of $\pi$ that is significantly simpler than a proof of a more general result, whereas we do know some ad hoc tricks that work for $e$. In principle this could change in the future if, for example, someone finds an amazingly simple ad hoc proof for the transcendence of $\pi$, or (less likely) a dramatic simplification of the proof of the transcendence of $e^\alpha$ for all nonzero algebraic $\alpha$.