[Math] Where does Segal’s category come from

at.algebraic-topologyloop-spacesuniversal-property

Segal's category $\Gamma$ is the skeleton of the category $\text{FinSet}_{\ast}$ of pointed finite sets. It is used to write down $\Gamma$-spaces, which are functors $\Gamma \to \text{Top}$ satisfying some conditions, and which model infinite loop spaces. I would like to be able to tell myself a story about this category which would explain in some sense why one might have come up with it as a candidate to be part of a delooping machine.

For comparison, here is the analogous story about $\text{FinSet}$: equipped with disjoint union, it is the free symmetric monoidal category on a commutative monoid. (I guess all of my stories are universal properties.) Since infinite loop spaces are in particular supposed to be like homotopy coherent commutative monoids I can see how one might have come up with $\text{FinSet}$ as a candidate to model infinite loop spaces, but not $\text{FinSet}_{\ast}$.

Riffing off of the above, it seems like $\text{FinSet}_{\ast}$, equipped with wedge sum, is the free symmetric monoidal category on something like a "copointed" commutative monoid; that is, a commutative monoid together with a map $\varepsilon : M \to 1$. The idea is that $\text{FinSet}_{\ast}$ can equivalently be thought of as the category of sets and partial functions, and throwing in a map $\varepsilon : M \to 1$ lets us model partial functions by using $\varepsilon$ to throw away the points at which a partial function isn't defined.

Why is this, and not $\text{FinSet}$, a reasonable category to use to model infinite loop spaces? (The inclusion of $\varepsilon : M \to 1$ is particularly strange because in any cartesian monoidal category, such as $\text{Top}$, it is unique because $1$ is the terminal object.) I guess $\varepsilon$ is needed to get an inclusion of $\Delta^{op}$ into $\Gamma$ so we can define the geometric realization of a $\Gamma$-space, but now I don't understand why there should be such an inclusion; the universal properties don't suggest it. The augmented simplex category $\Delta_a$ is the free monoidal category on a monoid, so the universal properties suggest instead a monoidal functor $\Delta_a \to \Gamma$.

Best Answer

Infinite loop spaces and spectra are intrinsically pointed, and the purpose of the basepoint is to build in basepoints, which give the units for the associated products. Let $T_*$ be the category of based objects in any cartesian monoidal category T. For an object $X$ of $T_*$, a covariant functor $X^*: F_* \longrightarrow T_*$ that sends the based set $n=\{0,1, \cdots, n\}$ with basepoint $0$ to $X^n$ is precisely a commutative monoid in $T$ with its unit element equal to the basepoint of $X$. Use of basepoints like this long precedes Segal. When $T$ is spaces, the James construction $JX$ is the free monoid on $X$ with unit the basepoint of $X$ and the infinite symmetric product $NX$ on $X$ is the free commutative monoid on $X$ with its unit element the basepoint of $X$, both suitably topologized.

In more detail, the morphisms of $F$ are generated under composition by injections, projections, and the based maps $\phi_n \colon n\to 1$ that send $i$ to $1$ for $1\leq i\leq n$. (Using the wedge sum, only $\phi_2$ need be added). The morphisms $\pi\colon m\to n$ such that $\phi^{-1}(i)$ has $0$ or $1$ element give a subcategory $\Pi$ of $F$, and the functor $X^*$ has underlying functor $\Pi\to T_*$ given by the injections (determined by the basepoint), projections, and permutations that are given by the assumption than $n \mapsto X^n$. The map $\phi_2$ gives a product $X\times X\longrightarrow X$ and, more generally, the $\phi_n \colon X^n\longrightarrow X$ give the unique $n$-fold product determined by $\phi_2$.

The point of infinite loop space theory is to build in the axioms of a commutative monoid up to "all higher coherence homotopies", and the genius of Segal was to see that the evident maps $\delta_i\colon n\longrightarrow 1$ that send $i$ to $1$ and $j$ to $0$ for $j\neq i$ can be used to build in these homotopies. Taking $T$ to be spaces, for a functor $Y\colon F_* \longrightarrow T_*$, we have based spaces $Y_n$, and the $\delta_i$ determine the Segal maps $\delta^n\colon Y_n \longrightarrow Y_1^n$. Requiring these maps to be homotopy equivalences for all $n\geq 0$ makes $Y_1$ a "commutative monoid up to all higher coherence homotopies", with canonical zigzag product $Y_1^2 \longleftarrow Y_2 \longrightarrow Y_1$ determined by $\delta^2$ and $\phi_2$.

I could go on forever about this. But maybe I'll just give the definition of the functor $K\colon \Delta^{op}\longrightarrow F_*$. I agree that its interpretation may not be obvious. Of course, $Kn = n$. For a map $\phi\colon n\longrightarrow m$ in $\Delta$, define $K\phi\colon m\longrightarrow n$ by sending $i$ to $j$ whenever $\phi(j-1) < i \leq \phi(j)$, where $1\leq j\leq n$, and sending $i$ to $0$ if there is no such $j$. Thus $$ (K\phi)^{-1}(j) = \{ i | \phi(j-1) < i \leq \phi(j)\} \ \ \text{for} \ \ 1\leq j\leq n. $$

Please excuse the lousy ad hoc notation (F= finite sets).

Related Question