[Math] Intuition behind generic points in a scheme

ag.algebraic-geometryintuitionschemes

In a scheme, each point is a generic point of its closure. In particular each closed point is a generic point of itself (the set containing it only), but that's perhaps of little interest. A point that's not closed, is probably more interesting, and there are no such thing in ordinary varieties.

What I have been wondering about is that there must be a good reason they are called generic points. Here are what I have got so far:

  • A non-closed generic point is not closed, so it cannot be cut out from the scheme by any polynomial equations in any affine patch, and thus it does not posses any extra algebraic property that's not shared by others.
  • A non-closed generic point is not a specialization of the scheme.

Are these correct? If not, what's the right intuition? Also, can the following statement be make more precise using the language of generic points?

  • A degree $n$ and a generic degree $m$ algebraic curves intersect at $n \cdot m$ distinct points in $\mathbb{P}^2$ (the planar Bezout's theorem)
  • Common solutions of $n$ polynomial systems in $n$ variables with generic complex coefficients in $\mathbb{C}^\ast$ are all isolated. (corollary of the Cheater's homotopy theorem)
  • The number of common isolated solutions of $n$ polynomial systems in $n$ variables with generic complex coefficients in $\mathbb{C}^\ast$ equals the mixed volume of the Newton polytopes of the system. (Bernshtein's theorem)
  • Generic points on a nonreduced scheme have isosingular structure (i.e., at all such points the local ring fail to be reduced in exactly the same way).

In each case I am familiar with their original meaning of the word generic, but I'm wondering if we can state the genericity conditions using the concept of generic points of schemes.

Best Answer

My favorite view on generic points is found in Mumford's book: Complex Projective Varieties, on page 2. It goes as roughly as follows:

Definition: Let $k \subset \mathbb{C}$ be a subfield of the complex numbers and $V$ an affine complex variety. A point $x \in V$ is $k$-generic if every polynomial with values in $k$ that vanishes on $x$, vanishes on all of $V$.

Proposition: If $\mathbb{C}/k$ has infinite transcendental degree, then every variety $V$ has a $k$-generic point.

Proof: Extend $k$ by all coefficients of a finite set of equations for $V$. Note that $\mathbb{C}/k$ has still infinite transcendental degree. But now $V$ becomes a variety over $k$ in a canonical way. The function field $L$ of $V$ is an $k$-extension of finite transcendental degree, and therefore can be embedded into $\mathbb{C}$. The images of the coordinate function $X_i \in L$ in $\mathbb{C}$ give the coordinates of a $k$-generic point.

For the relation to the generic point $\eta \in V$ from scheme theory note the following:

  • If we define a $k$-Zariski topology on $V(\mathbb{C})$ defined by polynomials over $k$, a $k$-generic point $x$ will be non-closed with closure $V$.
  • The field $K(x)/k$ generated by the coefficients of $x$, is canonically isomorphic to the function field $L=K(V)$, which is the residue field of the generic point $K(\eta)$.

From the abstract perspective the function field $L=K(\eta)$ is as good as $K(x)$, if not better, because it does not depend on choices. Moreover, all $k$-linear algebraic operations cant tell a difference between $\eta$ and $x$.

Related Question