[Math] general notion of semigroup action

ct.category-theoryra.rings-and-algebrassemigroups-and-monoids

The analogous result to Cayley’s theorem or Yoneda lemma in semigroup theory represents semigroups as semigroups of functions from a set to itself. This suggests that a semigroup action consists of a semigroup $S$, a set $A$, and a mapping of the elements of the semigroup $S$ to functions from the set $A$ to itself. But the analogous result for inverse semigroups requires partial symmetries, i.e. partial functions instead of total functions. But if we allow partial functions, then what do we do with removable singularities?

Here comes the desire to turn all this into "somebody else's problem", by using a general definition of semigroup action in terms of category theory. We can then work in the category of sets and (total) functions, if we don't need partial functions for the semigroup action. If we need partial functions, then we can work in the category of sets and partial functions. And if we worry about removable singularities, then we can work in the appropriate category where these are removable.

Edit (because of requests for clarification): Before going into details why it is unclear to me whether this proposed "solution" will fix the issues of the apparent "incompatibility" between semigroup action and the inverse semigroup representation theorem, here are questions that I "hope" can be answered:

  • How does the definition of semigroup action in terms category theory look like?
  • (main question) Does this definition make sense when applied to an inverse semigroup? Does it lead to the intended representation theorem if used with the category of sets and partial function?
  • Is there an analogous definition of groupoid action? Are the various connections between semigroups and groupoids compatible with these definitions of an action?

But how should such a definition look like? I'm not sure, but let's look at a (potential) similar definition for groupoid action: A groupoid action relative to a category $\mathcal C$ would be a groupoid $\mathcal G$ and a functor $\mathcal G\to \mathcal C$. In analogy to this, one could interpret a monoid as a category with a single object, a monoid action as a single object category $\mathcal M$ and a functor $\mathcal M\to \mathcal C$. A semigroup action would then be defined as a subsemigroup of a corresponding monoid action.

One problem I have is that if there were such a thing as a semigroupoid (there is: it's called a category…), it would be easy to interpret a small semigroupoid (and hence also a small groupoid) as a semigroup. (Add a new absorbing element and use it to define the result of any undefined composition from the semigroupoid.) But can one define a semigroup action in such a way that also the semigroupoid action can be interpreted appropriately in terms of semigroup action? This doesn't mean that the above definition won't work, maybe one just has to switch to a corresponding category of categories for being able to interpret it appropriately.


Side note One general issue for me related to the proposed "solution" is that I'm not too familiar with the treatment of partial homomorphisms within category theory. The category of pointed sets "hinted at" by Qiaochu Yuan makes it "crystal clear" how partial homomorphisms work in the case of sets. But is the situation for other (concrete) categories really as "straightforward" as this? Andrej Bauer suggested some references, and the topic also seems to be discussed in some category theory texts in connection with "limits and colimits", where a construction based on subobjects, equivalence classes and pullbacks is described. I will have to read and understand these.

Best Answer

Thanks to Andrej Bauer to drawing my attention to this question.

This is definitely related to restriction categories and I do recommend the articles by Steve Lack and myself ("Restriction categories I" TCS 2002). However, I though it may be useful to say a word or two about how the question relates to our development.

(1) There is, to start with, the issue of "units": being category theorists by training we (Steve and I) tended to assume units are present and preserved. An inverse semigroup (semicategory) of course can always be completed to an inverse monoid (category) or alternatively (and more interestingly) one can split the idempotents to get and inverse category. Both directions do allow one to keep (with some extra structure) all the information about one's start point. For example in the latter case one needs some information about what glues together into an object -- this leads one into a version of Ehresmann's "pseudo-groups" ... the multi-object version of all this, as far as I know, has not been systematically developed. Mark Lawson is the goto man on this!

(2) Given that one accepts one has units then restriction categories have a lot to say about representation theory:

Restriction categories give a very clean algebraic approach to partiality. There is a long (categorical and non-categorical) history behind this notion. For an appreciation of this see my paper with Ernie Manes (Boolean and classical restriction categories, MSCS 2009). However, the point is the categorical expression is very natural and is captured in just four identities.

An inverse category is a restriction category in which every map is a partial isomorphism. Thus an inverse category is to a restriction category what a groupoid is to an ordinary category. In particular, a one object inverse category is an inverse monoid ...

(3) There are two (main) representation theorems on restriction categories (see my paper with Steve).

(i) The first simply states that every restriction category is a full subcategory of a partial map category. This is a sanity check: it says the notion successfully completely captures "partiality".

(ii) The second -- and more relevant to this discussion -- says there is a full and faithful representation of a restriction category as a partial map category of a presheaf category. This is a genuine representation theorem and is a strengthening of the traditional Wagner-Preston theorem (as it gives a full and faithful embedding rather than just a faithful one). The theorem also gives a basic representation theorem for inverse categories as they are special restriction categories. The theorem is closely related to the Yoneda lemma (of course) but also requires the "right" notion of partiality on the presheaf category.

I hope this helps.

-robin

Related Question