Why is $V(xy)$ the (geometrically correct) union of the two axis (as a scheme)

affine-schemesalgebraic-geometrycategorical-logiccategory-theoryschemes

Consider $\newcommand{\Spec}{\operatorname{Spec}}V(xy) \subset \Spec \mathbb C[x,y]$ as a closed subscheme. We think of $V(xy)$ as the union of the two axis in $\mathbb A_\mathbb C^2$. But why?

The category of $\mathbb C$-schemes can be embedded into a larger category of sheaves on $\newcommand{\Aff}{\operatorname{Aff}}\Aff_\mathbb C = \mathbb C\operatorname{-Alg}^{\operatorname{op}}$ equipped with some Gorthendieck topology (etale, Zariski, flat, I don't know which is best). The correspondig sheaf topos is famously a model of some of the axioms synthetic differential geometry in the sense that we have infinitesimals. The affine line has (in the internal language) elements which are not not zero, but which aren't zero either and which square to zero. In the internal language the subspace $V(xy)$ is precisely$$V(xy) = \{(x,y):\mathbb A_\mathbb C^2|\,xy=0\}$$The space $V(x)$ on the other hand has the description
$V(x) = \{(x,y):\mathbb A_\mathbb C|x=0\}$. The join of $V(x)$ and $V(y)$ in the sheaf topos $\operatorname{Sh}(\operatorname{Aff},\tau)$ is for tautological reasons $$V(x)\vee_{\operatorname{Sh}(\operatorname{Aff},\tau)} V(y) = \{(x,y):\mathbb A_\mathbb C^2\,|\, x=0 \,\vee\, y=0 \}$$
But this is not the same as $V(xy)$ if the infinitesimal object $D= \{x:\mathbb A_\mathbb C\,|\,x^2=0\}$ of the affine line is non-trivial. In other words: $V(xy)$ seems a little to thick at the origin to be the union of $V(x)$ and $V(y)$.

I have asked a related question on math overflow.

Context: I am working with the functorial approach to algebraic geometry. Here you take the category of commutative rings, take its opposite $\Aff$ and equip it with a Grothendieck-topology. Then you look at functors $X:\text{cRing}\to \text{Set}$, equivalently presheaves on $\Aff$. A scheme $X$ in the usual locally ringed space style gives rise to a functor $h_X = \operatorname{Hom}_{\operatorname{Sch}}(-,X):\operatorname{Sch}^{op}\to \operatorname{Set}$ which in turn can be restricted along the inclusion $\operatorname{cRing} \to\operatorname{Sch}^{op}$ to give presheaf on the opposite of the category of rings. It turns out that this construction is fully faithful, and it makes the category of schemes a full subcategory of $\operatorname{Pr}(\Aff)$. So one can try to identify the category of schemes directly in $\operatorname{Pr}(\Aff)$ and develop scheme theory completly from this perspective. This is possible and not hard. The category of schemes one gets is embedded into the larger category of sheaves on the Zariski site. The right words to look for online are "gros Zariski topos" for example.

Best Answer

Well, if you are restricting your attention to schemes, there is simply not any better option. One way of saying this is that $V(xy)$ is the smallest closed subscheme that contains both $V(x)$ and $V(y)$. This just amounts to the algebraic fact that any element of $\mathbb{C}[x,y]$ which is divisible by both $x$ and $y$ must be divisible by $xy$. Another way to make this precise is to say that $V(xy)$ is the pushout of $V(x)$ and $V(y)$ over their intersection $V(x,y)$ in the category of schemes. So, if you restrict your attention to the the world of schemes, there just does not exist any better candidate to call the union of the two lines.

Your observation that this is not true in the larger sheaf topos is closely related to the fact that the algebraic fact above is not stable under base-change: if you map $\mathbb{C}[x,y]$ to some other $\mathbb{C}$-algebra, then the images of $x$ and $y$ may no longer have the property that any element divisible by both $x$ and $y$ is divisible by $xy$. In the context of schemes, this is the fact that the operation of taking unions of closed subschemes is not stable under base-change. Explicitly, for instance, if you pull back to the diagonal line $V(x-y)$ in $\mathbb{A}^2$, then $V(x)$ and $V(y)$ both become just the reduced point at the origin, but $V(xy)$ becomes a non-reduced thickened version.

Related Question