Understanding the Egorov Theorem

measure-theoryreal-analysis

The Egorov Theorem state:

Suppose $\{f_k\}$ is a squence of measurable functions defined on a measurable set $E$ with $m(E)<\infty$. Assume $f_k\rightarrow f$ almost everywhere on $E$. Given $\varepsilon>0$, we can find a closed set $A_\varepsilon\subset E$ such that $m(E-A_\varepsilon)\leq\varepsilon$ and $f_k\rightarrow f$ uniformly on $A_\varepsilon$.

I want to understand correctly what this theorem says.

My Questions:

  1. Is my interpretation correct?

You have a function $f$ that can be approximated, in a almost everywhere point-wise convergent-sense, by a sequence of measurable functions on a measurable (finite) set $E$. If you throw me an arbitrarily small number $\varepsilon>0$, I can always find a subset of $E$ contained in $E$ that is very close to the actual $E$ where the sequence of measurable functions converge uniformly to $f$ on that very similar domain, $A_\varepsilon$.

  1. Why is this theorem significant?

  2. I think I am not used to the term "approximation of a function by a sequence of functions" is equivocated to the clauses "the sequence converges to $f$ point-wise" or "the sequence converges to $f$ uniformly". So does this mean, when we say, we are approximating a function by a sequence of functions, we are looking at either point-wise or uniform convergence? Is this the language of approximation in the space of functions?

Best Answer

I just want to drill into your second question: why is this theorem significant. Postmortes already gave a summary of that in this answer, but I want to give a bit more detail. Without understanding the proof of this theorem, even looking at what it's saying, one can be amazed. To see why, let's start with a classic general rule involving quantifiers. Suppose we have some predicate $P(x, y)$ with $x \in X$ and $y \in Y$. Then the following general rules holds:

$$\exists x \in X \;\forall y \in Y \;P(x, y) \implies \forall y \in Y \; \exists x \in X \;P(x, y)$$

In other words, if there is some fixed $x$, over which the predicate holds for all $y$, then it is certainly true that at each $y$, there is some $x$ such that the predicate holds: just choose the same fixed $x$ at each $y$. However, and this is the key point: the converse is not true in general: just because for each $y$ we can find some $x$, dependent on that $y$, that satisfies the predicate, it doesn't mean we can find a single $x$ satisfying the predicate across all $y$.

At this point, let's step into a concrete counterexample which will serve to show why the converse of the above is not true and will also get us closer to the significance of Egorov's result. Let's forget about measures for the moment and just consider uniform vs. pointwise convergence. Suppose we have a set $Z$ and a sequence of functions $f_n$ on that set. Pointwise convergence of $f_n \to f$ on $Z$ is defined as:

$$\forall \epsilon \in \Bbb R \; \forall z \in Z \; \exists m \in \Bbb N \; \forall i > m \; |f_i(z) - f(z)| < \epsilon$$

Whereas uniform convergence is defined as:

$$\forall \epsilon \in \Bbb R \; \exists m \in \Bbb N \; \forall z \in Z \; \forall i > m \; |f_i(z) - f(z)| < \epsilon$$

Now, while there surely are more quantifiers at play, if we look closely enough we can see that the two definitions differ only in terms of the ordering of a consecutive existential and universal quantifier. This immediately lets us conclude, using the general rule above, that uniform convergence implies pointwise convergence. Now let's use this concrete example to see why pointwise convergence doesn't imply uniform convergence. Let $Z = \Bbb R$ and let $f_n(z) = z/n$.

Clearly for any given $z$, $f_n(z) \rightarrow 0$ as $n \rightarrow \infty$. That means, for any $\epsilon$ and $z$ we can pick an $m$ such that for all functions $f_i$ with $i > m$, the difference with $f$ is bounded i.e.

$$|f_i(z) - f(z)| < \epsilon$$

However, given that same $\epsilon$, there is no fixed $m$ that will give us such a bound for all $z$. You can show that by contradiction, assuming there is some such $m$. But since $f_i(z) = z/i$, we can always choose some $z$ to make $f_i(z)$ as large as we want, for any given $i$. So for any $i > m$, we can choose such a $z$, contradicting the assumption that there is some $m$ giving uniform convergence.

So now moving on to Egorov's result. Why is it significant? Well, to begin with, it's not immediately intuitive, because it might appear to go against the above counterexample, which shows that we can't in general pull an existential quantifier outside of a universal quantifier. Any theorem that seems to defy pre existing intuition is in itself useful, because it strengthens our understanding further and allows us to reset our intuition to better understand the underlying theory: in this case measure theory.

As Postmortes argues, it's also practically very useful. At a very cheap cost, it manages to strengthen pointwise convergence to uniform convergence. The price we have to pay is minimal: just remove a tiny little set that we can make as small as we want and boom! We get uniform convergence on the rest of the set. In other words, in this special case, we are allowed to pull the existential quantifier outside of the universal quantifier- once we remove a tiny bit of the domain.

Why else this is significant is that it provides great motivation for using measure theory. Without measure theory, we wouldn't be able to conclude the result of Egorov. In particular, the key ingredient that measure theory brings into the mix is continuity of the measure- this continuity, combined with the fact that the sequence of functions is countable, allows us to shrink the set we are removing to be as small as we like, and leave a remaining set where uniform convergence holds.