Topology – Universal Property of Subspace Topology

category-theorygeneral-topology

It is said in wikipedia, nlab and Terilla that subspace has a universal property.

Universal property for the subspace topology. For every topological space $(Z, \tau_Z)$ and every function $f : Z \to Y$, $f$ is continuous if and only if $i \circ f : Z \to X$ is continuous.

Here's a picture

$$
\begin{array}{ccc}
{} & {} & X \\
{} & \overset{i \circ f}{\nearrow} & \uparrow i \\
Z & \underset{f}{\to} & Y
\end{array}
$$

One should think of the universal property stated above as a property that may be attributed to a topology on $Y$. At this point, you may think that some topologies have this property and some do not. Theorem $1$ means that the subspace topology on $Y$, as previously defined, does have this universal property. Furthermore, the subspace topology is the only topology on $Y$ with this property. Let's prove it.

But, as I know, universal property is some sort of 'initial' or 'final' property in another category such as object: $X\xrightarrow f Y, \forall Y, f$ and morphism $\sigma: Y\rightarrow Z$ makes the triangle $X\xrightarrow f Y$ and $X\xrightarrow g Z$ commute, thats to say $g = \sigma f$. However, I cannot see any universal property in this triangle, since $i\circ f$ is not 'any' morphism, but have connections with what isn't known yet – the morphism $f$.

So, how can we understand this as a universal property ? Or, why a universal property can have connection with 'f'?

Best Answer

This universal property is to mediate between arbitrary functions (defined on the underlying set of some space) and continuous functions (which make reference to the topology). This should make some sense, since we're already given $Y$ (and thus, access to functions into $Y$) and we're trying to choose the right topology to equip $Y$ with.

Here's another place you may have seen this idea: We know the product of $(X,\tau_X)$ and $(Y, \tau_Y)$ must have $X \times Y$ as its underlying set. But how can we tell whether a function $f : (Z, \tau_Z) \to X \times Y$ "should" be continuous? Well we say that $f$ is continuous if and only if both $\pi_X \circ f : (Z, \tau_Z) \to (X, \tau_X)$ and $\pi_Y \circ f : (Z, \tau_Z) \to (Y, \tau_Y)$ are continuous! So you see, we've been given a function $f$ on underlying sets, and the universal property tells us whether or not $f$ is continuous.

In your example, we have a similar question: How can we tell when an arbitrary function $f : (Z, \tau_Z) \to Y \ (\subseteq X)$ should be continuous? Well, we want $f$ to be continuous if and only if $\iota \circ f : (Z, \tau_Z) \to (X, \tau_X)$ is!

I agree that these don't look like the kinds of simple universal properties that you might be used to. That's basically because (as I said at the start of this answer) they're universal properties mediating which maps in $\mathsf{Set}$ lift to maps in $\mathsf{Top}$, rather than the usual universal properties which govern which maps we can construct at all. But we can still formulate these as universal properties that you might recognize (it just takes some work). If you like, there is a lattice of possible topologies you can put on $Y$, and the universal property is saying that there's an initial/terminal object in this lattice of possible topologies (viewed as a thin category).

This can be made precise with the language of "lifts of $U$-structured sources/sinks", central to the definition of a topologically concrete category (that is, a category whose relationship to $\mathsf{Set}$ is structurally similar to the relationship between $\mathsf{Top}$ and $\mathsf{Set}$). You can read more about these ideas in Adamek, Herrlich, and Strecker's The Joy of Cats.


I hope this helps ^_^

Related Question