Rudin proof for compact subsets $\{ K_{\alpha} \}$ (theorem 2.36) — Contrapositive or contradiction

compactnessgeneral-topologyproof-explanation

I am having doubts about Theorem 2.36 pasted below. I was able to follow all the steps individually, but I don’t see how this is a proof by contradiction. It seems to be it is a proof by contrapositive.

enter image description here

That is because, we are assuming intersection of all $\{ K_{\alpha} \}$ is empty, then showing that intersection of an arbitrarty finite subcollection $K_1 \cap K_{\alpha_{1}} \cap \cdot\cdot\cdot \cap K_{\alpha_{n}} = \phi$.

What am I missing here? Why is this not proof by contrapositive?

Best Answer

Whether one sees it as a proof by contradiction or as a proof of the contrapositive depends on whether one assumes that the $K_\alpha$ have the finite intersection property. If one makes that assumption, then the argument is indeed a proof by contradiction: the further assumption that the intersection of all of the $K_\alpha$ is empty leads to a conclusion that contradicts that contradicts the starting assumption. That further assumption must therefore be false.

If one does not make that initial assumption, the same argument proves that the $K_\alpha$ do not have the finite intersection property and thus demonstrates the contrapositive of the stated result. I prefer to view it as a proof of the contrapositive, but both views are logically defensible, and Rudin evidently chose to adopt the other view.

Added: The difference is in the logical structure of the proof of an implication $A\implies B$. In a direct proof we assume $A$ and somehow derive $B$. In a proof of the contrapositive we assume $\neg B$ and somehow prove $\neg A$; this direct proof of the contrapositive of course establishes the logically equivalent original implication $A\implies B$.

In a proof by contradiction we assume $A$ and $\neg B$ and somehow derive a contradiction. This shows that $A$ and $\neg B$ cannot both be true, so if $A$ is true, then $\neg B$ must be false and therefore $B$ must be true. It sometimes happens in the in deriving the contradiction we never really use the assumption that $A$ is true: we actually use only the assumption $\neg B$ and get our contradiction (with the assumption $A$) by deriving $\neg A$ from $\neg B$. In that case, which is what we have here, we’ve presented what could have been a direct proof of the contrapositive in the logical form of a proof by contradiction, and technically that form makes it a proof by contradiction. It just didn’t have to be one. We didn’t use the assumption $A$ at any point in the actual mechanics of the argument: it served only to be contradicted.