Number Theory – Converse of Euclid’s Lemma

elementary-number-theory

Im having trouble proving the converse of Euclid's lemma, and was wondering if anyone could point me in the right direction.

Euclid's Lemma: Let $p$ be a prime number and $a$ and $b$ be natural numbers greater than 1, then if $p|ab$ we know $p|a$ or $p|b$

Converse: For some number $p$, if for all natural numbers $a$ and $b$ greater than 1, $p|ab$ implies $p|a$ or $p|b$, then $p$ is prime.

I tried showing that $p$ had only factors 1 and $p$, but I didn't really manage to make any progress, I'm just really not sure where to start, I'd really appreciate any help, thanks.

Best Answer

If $p$ is not prime, then there are $a,b \neq p$ with $p = ab$. Now $p \mid ab$ but $p \not \mid a, p \not \mid b$.

longer version:

We already have the implication

($p$ prime) $\implies$ (if $p \mid a \cdot b$, then $p \mid a$ or $p \mid b$)

We want to show the implication

(if $p \mid a \cdot b$, then $p \mid a$ or $p \mid b$) $\implies$ ($p$ prime)

We do this my contraposition:

($p$ not prime) $\implies$ (there exist $a,b$ with $p \mid a \cdot b$ and $p \not \mid a, p \not \mid b$)

Now, if $p$ is not prime, then there is a factorization $p = a \cdot b$ with $a \neq p \neq b$. Hence we have $p \mid a \cdot b$, but $p \not \mid a, p \not \mid b$, which shows the above implication.

Related Question