[Math] One point compactification of the rationals is not second countable

compactnessgeneral-topology

As a counter example to show that second countable is a property which is not preserved under a continuous function, I consider the rationals under the discrete topology, which is second countable, and the existence of any other countable space that is not second countable is sufficient.

I chose the one point compactification of the rationals as such a space because several sources say this is true, but I am very lost on how to go about proving this. I have studied other questions on this site about the compact subsets of Q, and aim to form an open set in Q* that couldn't possibly be formed by a countable union of open sets, but I do not see how this is possible.

I appreciate any insight. Thanks

Best Answer

It is true that the one-point compactification of the rationals with their usual topology is not second countable: it is not first countable at the new point. Unfortunately, neither of the proofs that come to mind is completely elementary. I’ll sketch the simpler one. Let $\Bbb Q^*$ be the one-point compactification of $\Bbb Q$ with the usual topology, and let $p$ be the point at infinity.

I’ll show first that $\Bbb Q^*$ is a $US$-space, meaning that no sequence in $\Bbb Q^*$ converges to more than one point. Let $\sigma=\langle x_n:n\in\Bbb N\rangle$ be a sequence in $\Bbb Q$ that converges in $\Bbb Q^*$. If $\sigma$ converges to some $x\in\Bbb Q$, the set $K=\{x\}\cup\{x_n:n\in\Bbb N\}$ is a compact subset of $\Bbb Q$, $\Bbb Q^*\setminus K$ is therefore an open nbhd of $p$ disjoint from $K$, and $\sigma$ does not converge to $p$. The subspace $\Bbb Q$ is Hausdorff, and all Hausdorff spaces are $US$-spaces, so $\sigma$ does not converge to any point of $\Bbb Q$ other than $x$, and $x$ is therefore the unique limit of $\sigma$. If $\sigma$ does not converge to any point of $\Bbb Q$, then of course its unique limit must be $p$. Thus, $\Bbb Q^*$ is a $US$-space.

$\Bbb Q^*$ is not Hausdorff: if $x\in\Bbb Q$, $x$ and $p$ cannot be separated by disjoint open sets. For suppose that $U$ is an open nbhd of $p$. Then $K=\Bbb Q^*\setminus U$ is a compact subset of $\Bbb Q$ and therefore nowhere dense in $\Bbb Q$, so $K$ cannot contain an open nbhd of $x$.

Finally, every first countable $US$-space is Hausdorff, so $\Bbb Q^*$ cannot be first countable. To see this, suppose that $X$ is a first countable $US$-space that is not Hausdorff, and let $x,y\in X$ be such that $U\cap V\ne\varnothing$ whenever $U$ and $V$ are open nbhds of $x$ and $y$, respectively. Suppose that $\{B_n:n\in\Bbb N\}$ is a countable open base at $x$, and $\{W_n:n\in\Bbb N\}$ is a countable open base at $y$. For each $n\in\Bbb N$ let $x_n\in B_n\cap W_n$; then $\langle x_n:n\in\Bbb N\rangle$ converges to both $x$ and $y$, contradicting the hypothesis that $X$ is a $US$-space. Thus, $X$ must be Hausdorff.

There are much easier examples of countable spaces that are not second countable. One is the Arens-Fort space; given a countable family $\mathscr{B}$ of open nbhds of the one non-isolated point of the space, it’s not hard to construct an open nbhd of that point that doesn’t contain any member of $\mathscr{B}$. If you know a little about ultrafilters, another fairly simple example is to let $p$ be a free ultrafilter on $\Bbb N$ and let $X=\{p\}\cup\Bbb N$. $\Bbb N$ has the discrete topology, and a local base at $p$ is $\big\{\{p\}\cup U:U\in p\big\}$. This is a subspace of the Katětov extension of $\Bbb N$, and I proved in this answer that it’s not first countable at $p$.

In this answer I described a couple more examples, one based on the ultrafilter space and one on the Arens-Fort space. They’re a bit more complicated, but they have some fairly nice properties: they’re zero-dimensional and Hausdorff and have no isolated points.

Related Question