Infinite Product – Measurable Spaces in Measure Theory

elementary-set-theorymeasure-theoryproduct-space

  1. Suppose there is a family (can be
    infinite) of measurable spaces. What
    are the usual ways to define a sigma
    algebra on their Cartesian product?

  2. There is one way in the context of
    defining product measure on
    planetmath. Let $(E_i, B_i)$ be
    measurable spaces, where $i \in I$
    is an index set, possibly infinite.
    We define their product as follows:

    • let $E= \prod_{i \in I} E_i$ , the Cartesian product of $E_i$,

    • let $B=\sigma((B_i)i \in I)$ , the smallest sigma algebra
      containing subsets of E of the
      form $\prod_{i \in I}B_i$ where
      $B_i=E_i$ for all but a finite
      number of $i \in I$ .

    I was wondering why it is required
    that "$B_i=E_i$ for all but a finite
    number of $i \in I$"?

Thanks and regards!


ADDED:

I was wondering if the product sigma algebra defined in 2 is the smallest sigma algebra such that any tuple composed of one measurable set from each individual sigma algebra is measurable?

Best Answer

This is a good question. I haven't yet worked out a complete answer myself, but Mariano's comment above is definitely part of it: the given product $\sigma$-algebra has the property which is analogous to that of the product topology (which it resembles and is surely modelled on): it is the smallest $\sigma$-algebra which makes all of the projections measurable.

Because of this, I believe that if you make a category out of all measurable spaces and measurable functions in the obvious way, the product $\sigma$-algebra you have defined turns out to be the categorical product: i.e., it satisfies the requisite universal mapping property. Again, this is the situation for the product topology.

But I think the rest of the explanation has to do with the fact that this $\sigma$-algebra gives you the theorems you want, just as the product topology -- and not the "box topology" for instance -- has nice properties, especially Tychonoff's theorem. (The product topology was introduced for the first time in Tychonoff's paper, and his theorem played a large role in convincing mathematicians that it was the "right" topology on an infinite Cartesian product.)

I'm not sure exactly what the analogous result to Tychonoff's theorem is here, but I do know that this "coarsest" product $\sigma$-algebra enables one to define arbitrary products of probability spaces: see this lovely paper of S. Saeki1 for an incredibly short proof of that. I hope it is at least clear where the "coarseness" of the chosen product $\sigma$-algebra comes in handy: if (say in the case of a countably infinite index set, to fix ideas) (added: Michael Greinecker's answer shows that countable products actually behave rather well, so let's instead think about uncountable products) we allowed arbitrary products $Y = \prod_{i} Y_i$ of measurable subsets $Y_i \subset X_i$ to be measurable, then what should the measure of $Y$ be? If the set of indices for which $\mu(Y_i) < 1$ is uncountable, the product (taking the net of finite subsets of $I$) must approach zero. By requiring $Y_i = X_i$ for almost every $i$, we get that $\mu_i(Y_i) = 1$ for almost every $i$ and the infinite product is really a finite product.

Is there more to the story than this? Is the above construction of the product probability measure the "right" analogue of Tychonoff's theorem in this context (is there even a "right" analogue of Tychonoff's theorem in this context?)? I'm not sure, and I would be interested to hear more from others.

1 Saeki, Sadahiro, A proof of the existence of infinite product probability measures, Am. Math. Mon. 103, No. 8, 682-683 (1996). ZBL0882.28005, MR1413587. Link to a snapshot in the Wayback Machine.

Related Question