Real Analysis – Does Every Ordered Field Have a Subfield Isomorphic to Q?

field-theoryordered-fieldsreal numbersreal-analysis

I'm going through the first chapter in a text on real analysis, which contains preliminaries on ordered fields, the real numbers, etc. Supposedly I had learned about such things already, in calculus, but I thought it wouldn't hurt to go over it again.

Up until the paragraph which is the subject of my question, everything is thoroughly proven and examples are provided. However the following excerpt just goes through facts, whose proof I cannot conceive:

Although $\mathbb Q$ is an archimedean field, these properties cannot be used to define $\mathbb Q$ since $\\$ there are many Archimedean ordered fields. What distinguishes $\mathbb Q$ from the other $\\$Archimedean ordered fields is that $(\mathbb Q,<)$ is the $smallest$ ordered field in the following sense: $\\$ if $(X,\prec)$ is an ordered field, then $X$ contains a sub-field which is (field) isomorphic to $\mathbb Q$.$\\$ Furthermore such an isomorphism preserves the order relation.

I've concatenated the paragraph a bit, so the text isn't idem from the book (if anyone wishes to know it's Phillips, An Introduction to Analysis and Integration Theory, Dover Publications). Also $\mathbb Q$ contains no proper subfields, and this can be verified by the apparently easy-to-prove fact that, if a field has characteristic zero, then it contains a subfield isomorphic to $\mathbb Q$. Then it remains to prove the preservation of order.

I'm guessing that some concepts from abstract algebra or field theory would easily suffice, but at the moment such topics are a bit over my head, so all I can think of doing is actually constructing the isomorphism $\phi:\mathbb Q\to\hat{\mathbb Q}$, where $\hat{\mathbb Q}$ is a certain subfield of $X$ in such a way that field operations are preserved, but I really can't come up with anything. So the question is: how do I construct this isomorphism, or, if there's a better way of proving this, how is it done? Thanks for any help.

Edit: Assume the existence of $(\mathbb Q,<)$ as an archimedean ordered field.

Best Answer

Any ordered field $F$ has characteristic $0$, so it contains a copy of $\mathbb{Z}$; by the universal property of the quotient field, the ring monomorphism $\mathbb{Z}\to F$ lifts to a monomorphism $\mathbb{Q}\to F$. We can identify $\mathbb{Q}$ with its image, so it's not restrictive to assume that $\mathbb{Q}\subseteq F$.

It's not really difficult: if $m/n\in\mathbb{Q}$, then we send it to $$ \frac{f(m)}{f(n)}\in F $$ where $f\colon \mathbb{Z}\to F$ is the (unique) monomorphism. Is this a field homomorphism? Just a check.

Now we come to the order. First of all, positive integers are positive in $(F,\prec)$: if $n>0$, then $$ n=\underbrace{1+1+\dots+1}_{\text{$n$ times}} $$ and therefore $0\prec n$. Conversely, if $n<0$, then $$ n=-(\,\underbrace{\,1+1\dots+1}_{\text{$-n$ times}}\,) $$ and so $n\prec0$.

Any element of $\mathbb{Q}$ can be represented as $m/n$ with $n>0$, because $a/b=(-a)/(-b)$, where $a,b\in F$, $b\ne0$. So, let $0\prec m/n$ in the ordering of $F$, with $n>0$. Then, by the properties of ordered fields, $$ 0\prec n\cdot\frac{m}{n}=m $$ and therefore $m>0$. So a rational which is positive in $(F,\prec)$ is also positive in the usual order. A rational which is negative in $(F,\prec)$ is the opposite of a positive rational (in both orders).

Related Question