Measure Theory – Can Sets of Cardinality $\aleph_1$ Have Nonzero Measure?

cardinalsdescriptive-set-theorymeasure-theoryset-theory

$\aleph_1$ is the cardinality of the countable ordinals. It is the least cardinal number greater than $\aleph_0$, and assuming the continuum hypothesis it's equal to $\mathfrak{c}$, the cardinality of the the real numbers.

My question is, is it possible for all $\aleph_1$ subsets of $\Bbb{R}$ to have Lebesgue measure $0$? This is, of course, impossible assuming the continuum hypothesis, because then all sets of real numbers would have measure $0$, which is absurd. But is $\mathsf{ZFC}$ + $\lnot\mathsf{CH}$ + "all subset of $\Bbb{R}$ of cardinality $\aleph_1$ have Lebesgue measure $0$" consistent? If not, what if we replaced Lebesgue measure with some other measure?

It may be worth noting that, although there may be subsets of $\Bbb{R}$ with cardinality $\aleph_1$, there are no subsets of $\Bbb{R}$ which have the order-type $\omega_1$ (the order-type of the countable ordinals) under the usual ordering on $\Bbb{R}$.

Any help would be greatly appreciated.

Thank you in Advance.

Best Answer

Of course assuming CH they can. But if $\aleph_1 < 2^{\aleph_0}$ then there is no measurable set of cardinality $\aleph_1$ having positive Lebesgue measure, so the answer to the question in the title is no. We can prove the following in ZFC without requiring additional axioms.

Proposition (ZFC). Every uncountable Borel subset of $\mathbb{R}$ has cardinality $2^{\aleph_0}$.

This is a corollary of the Perfect Set Theorem (every uncountable Borel set contains a perfect set, i.e. a set with no isolated points, and any such set has cardinality at least $2^{\aleph_0}$). For a proof, see Theorem 13.6 of Kechris's Classical Descriptive Set Theory.

Corollary (ZFC). Every Lebesgue measurable subset of $\mathbb{R}$ with cardinality less than $2^{\aleph_0}$ has Lebesgue measure zero.

Proof. Every Lebesgue measurable set $E$ can be written $E = B \cup N$ where $B$ is Borel and $m(N) = 0$; in particular $m(E) = m(B)$. But if $|E| < 2^{\aleph_0}$ then $|B| < 2^{\aleph_0}$, so by the previous proposition $B$ is countable and hence $m(B) = 0$.

Related Question