Characterizing infinite Dedekind-finite sets.

foundationsinfinitylogicset-theory

Is the following true in $\text{ZF}$?

A set $X$ is an infinite Dedekind-finite set if and only for every bijection $f: X \to X$ there exists a partition $X = C \cup Y$ with $C$ a finite set and $Y$ an infinite Dedekind-finite set such that $f(C) = C$. Moreover, the set $X$ can be completely partitioned into finite sets $C_\iota$ such that $f(C_\iota) = C_\iota$ with $\iota$ ranging over an infinite index set.

My work

This research endeavor came about from my work found here.

I couldn't find this question as a duplicate but before getting bogged down in the details I wanted to just get some quick feedback (please excuse the laziness – I am not an expert in set theory).

Best Answer

This is (mostly) true.

In one direction, given $f:X\rightarrow X$, for each $a\in X$ we can consider the orbit of $a$ under $f$, $$orb_f(a)=\{f^{z}(a): z\in\mathbb{Z}\}.$$ If $X$ is Dedekind-finite, each $orb_f(a)$ must itself be finite, and by definition we have $f(orb_f(a))=orb_f(a)$ and $X=\bigcup_{a\in X}orb_f(a)$.

In the other direction, suppose $X$ is Dedekind-infinite. WLOG let $X=\mathbb{Z}\sqcup Y$. Then consider the self-bijection $f$ which shifts $\mathbb{Z}$ via $z\mapsto 1+z$ and is the identity on $Y$. Clearly we cannot partition $X$ into finite $f$-invariant pieces. However, at the same time we may still be forced to have some finite nonempty $f$-fixed sets: namely, if $Y$ itself is infinite but Dedekind-finite. So there is a slight subtlety there: the strong version of your property fully characterizes Dedekind-finiteness, but the weak version (the guaranteed existence of just one such $C$) doesn't.

Related Question